In Conversation With Steven Pinker

Posted by admin on


By Oliver Burkeman

In short, its not hard to find anecdotes that seem to contradict a guiding principle behind much of Pinkers work which is that science and human reason are, slowly but unmistakably, making the world a better place.

Repeatedly during our conversation, I seek to puncture the silver-haired professors quietly relentless optimism. If the ongoing tolls of war and violence cant do it, what about the prevalence in America of unscientific beliefs about the origins of life? Or the devastating potential impacts of climate change, paired with the news also released in the week we meet that 23 per cent of Americans dont believe its happening, up seven percentage points in just eight months?

I try. But it proves far from easy.

At first glance Pinkers implacable optimism, though in keeping with his sunny demeanour and stereotypically Canadian friendliness, presents a puzzle. His stellar career which includes two Pulitzer Prize nominations for his books How the Mind Works (1997) and The Blank Slate: The modern denial of human nature (2002) has been defined, above all, by support for the fraught notion of human nature: the contention that genetic predispositions account in hugely significant ways for how we think, feel and act, why we behave towards others as we do, and why we excel in certain areas rather than others.

This has frequently drawn Pinker into controversy as in 2005, when he offered a defence of Larry Summers, then Harvards President, who had suggested that the under-representation of women in science and maths careers might be down to innate sex differences.

The possibility that men and women might differ for reasons other than socialisation, expectations, hidden biases and barriers is very close to an absolute taboo, Pinker tells me. He faults books such as Lean In, by Facebooks chief operating officer, Sheryl Sandberg, for not entertaining the notion that men and women might not have identical life desires. But he also insists that taking the possibility of such differences seriously need not lend any justification to policies or prejudices that exclude women from positions of expertise or power.

Even if there are sex differences, theyre differences in the means of two overlapping populations, so for any [stereotypically female] trait you care to name, therell be many men who are more extreme than most women, and vice versa. So as a matter of both efficiency and of fairness, you should treat every individual as an individual, and not prejudge them.

It is generally assumed that anyone who takes human nature seriously will be a fatalist, and probably politically conservative. If were pre-wired to be how we are, the reasoning goes, we might as well accept it and give up on hopes of any change. One way of interpreting Pinkers most recent book, The Better Angels of Our Nature, is as an 800-page doorstopper of a riposte to this idea. Not only can we change, but when it comes to arguably the most important measure of improvement the violence we inflict on each other we actually have changed, to an almost incredible degree.

I had very often come across the objection that if human nature exists including some ugly motives like revenge, dominance, greed and lust then that would imply its pointless to try to improve the human condition, because humans are innately depraved, says the 59-year-old, whose distinctive appearance today he is sporting black cowboy boots frequently gets him stopped in the street. Or theres an alternative objection: that we ought to improve our lot, and therefore, it cannot be the case that human nature exists.

Pinker puts all this down to a fear that acknowledging human nature would subvert any attempt to improve the human condition. Better Angels argues that this is a misunderstanding of what human nature means. It shouldnt be identified with a certain set of behaviours; rather, we have a complex variety of predispositions, violent and peaceful, that can be activated in different ways by different environments. The books title, drawn from Abraham Lincolns first inaugural address, is a poetic allusion to the parts of human nature that can overcome the nastier parts, he explains.

But Better Angels is notable above all for the sheer weight of evidence it amasses, culled from forensic archaeology, government statistics, town records, and studies by atrocitologists of historical genocides and other mass killings. The book demonstrates that homicides, calculated as a proportion of the worlds population at any given point, have plummeted; when you look at the numbers this way, World War II wasnt the worst single atrocity in history, but more like the tenth.

Pinker dwells, in sometimes unnerving detail, on horrifying methods of torture once considered routine. The Heretics Fork had a pair of sharp spikes at each end, he writes, in what is definitely not the most appalling passage. One end was propped under the victims jaw and the other at the base of his neck, so that as his muscles became exhausted he would impale himself in both places.

Human nature or no human nature, Pinker says, its just a brute fact that we dont throw virgins into volcanoes any more. We dont execute people for shoplifting a cabbage. And we used to.

He offers a multi-pronged explanation for this decline, from the rise of the state and of cities, to literacy, trade and democracy. Whether this constitutes an across-the-board endorsement of scientific rationality may be debated. (Like other latter-day partisans of Enlightenment values, the critic John Gray wrote, Pinker prefers to ignore the fact that many Enlightenment thinkers have been doctrinally anti-liberal, while quite a few have favoured the large-scale use of political violence.) But its hard to question the basic finding that your chances of meeting a sticky end, all else being equal, are vastly lower in 2014 than they were in 1014.

If Pinkers message has proved hard for some to swallow, that may be because our standards are improving even faster than our actual behaviour, giving the misleading impression that things are getting worse. Hate attacks on Muslims are deplorable, and they ought to be combated, and it reflects well that were concerned when they do occur, Pinker says. But by the standards of past pogroms and ethnic cleansings, theyre in the noise: this is not a phenomenon of the same magnitude as the ethnic expulsions of decades past.

Weve even witnessed the emergence of whole new categories of condemnable acts. Take bullying, says Pinker: The President of the United States gave a speech denouncing bullying! When I was a child, this would have been worthy of satire. As we continue to construct a social environment that activates more and more of our peaceable dispositions, and fewer and fewer of our aggressive ones, the remaining instances of bad behaviour stick out like ever-sorer thumbs.

Whats more, evolutionary psychology, one of Pinkers several specialisms, can explain why. For reasons that long ago made excellent sense, our brains are adapted to focus on bad news over good, vivid threats over vague ones, and recent horrors over historically distant atrocities. Our elevated levels of anxiety about the future might actually be a sign of reasons triumph.

It could be interpreted as a sign of our growing up, Pinker says. We worry about more things, because we know that there are more things to worry about. Every time we go to a restaurant, we worry we might be ingesting saturated fats, or carcinogens. For my parents generation, the main concern about food was: Does it taste delicious?

Many of Pinkers most ambitious ideas about science and human morality have their origins in a seemingly trivial observation about irregular verbs. Building on the groundbreaking linguistic ideas of Noam Chomsky, Pinker proposed that certain simple language errors committed by young children capture the essence of language itself.

When a three-year-old says I eated the ice cream or we holded the kittens, she is, Pinker observes, following a grammar rule correctly, and making a mistake only because we happen to suspend the rule for those verbs in English. Since she couldnt have learned eated or holded by simply imitating adult speakers, this points to the presence of innate cognitive machinery a language instinct, to quote the title of Pinkers 1994 book that enables a young child to construct novel linguistic forms by following rules.

(Irregular verbs have an even more intimate role in Pinkers life: he met his wife, the philosopher Rebecca Goldstein, through an email exchange after he mentioned her correct use of the past participle stridden in his book Words and Rules.)

Years later, in 2007s The Stuff of Thought, he extended this reasoning to the structures of mentalese, the wordless language of thought that he argues we use to think in. When, for example, we use spatial language to talk about time as in a long day, or bringing a meeting forward might we be relying on an in-built, pre-linguistic tendency to think about the abstract notion of time by analogy to space, something far more concretely graspable to an early human concerned with food, shelter and survival?

This view of the mind as a set of modules evolved to confront specific cognitive challenges on the Pleistocene savannah is most ambitiously on display in How the Mind Works, a dazzling effort to reverse engineer all of our mental capacities, asking for what purposes each might have been selected. Love, humour, war, jealousy, the disgust we feel at the idea of eating certain animals but not others, religous food taboos, compulsive lying: none of them escape the blade of Pinkers rationalist scalpel.

Assuming you buy the books general approach, it is almost impossible after reading it to cling to the romantic notion that there might be more to our inner lives than the brute facts of biology and natural selection. The notable exception is how the brain causes sentience, or conscious awareness: after a long discussion on the topic,Pinker finally concludes: Beats me! Theres reason to believe, he argues, that humans may simply lack the mental capacity ever to solve the mindbody problem.

But the broader philosophical question how far science can, or should, reach into the life of the mind got a disputatious airing last year, when Pinker wrote an essay for the New Republic entitled Science is not your enemy. It was motivated in part by reports on both sides of the Atlantic about declining student enrolments in humanities subjects, and was Pinkers intervention in the long-running debate over scientism: are science and scientists guilty of attempting to colonise areas of intellectual life where they dont belong?

Rather than denying that this was a real phenomenon, as numerous scientists have, Pinker audaciously claimed it was a good thing providing you defined scientism correctly. Humanities scholars had themselves to blame, he implied, for the decline of their fields: by insisting on remaining inside departmental silos, resistant to new approaches, theyd helped guarantee their growing irrelevance. Science was not engaged upon an imperialistic drive to occupy the humanities, he wrote. The promise of science is to enrich and diversify the intellectual tools of humanistic scholarship, not to obliterate them.

In a furious response, entitled Crimes against humanities, the New Republics literary editor, Leon Wieseltier, accused Pinker of denying the very possibility of valid yet non-scientific knowledge. How absurd, he argued, to imagine that a scientific analysis of a painting a chemical breakdown of its pigments and textures, and so on could be the only thing worth saying about it. Pinker calls this a paranoid interpretation of his argument. How could an understanding of perception of colour, of form, of lighting, of shading, of content such as faces and landscapes not enrich our understanding of art?

Yet if Wieseltiers retort was overheated, he may still have a point. Pinker wasnt and isnt merely calling on scholars from different disciplines to talk to each other more. His argument is that any scholar committed to the idea that the world is intelligible is doing science. The great thinkers of the Age of Reason and the Enlightenment were scientists, he wrote, naming various philosophers.

It seems to follow from this that non-scientific scholarship doesnt help make the world intelligible, but Pinker will have none of it. Im married to a humanities scholar. I collaborate with humanities scholars. Im in fields like linguistics, where deans dont know whether its the humanities or not, he says. Many humanities scholars particularly here at Harvard and MIT, but elsewhere too find it very exciting that there might be new ways of approaching old problems, and an influx of new ideas. I mean, who in their right mind could defend insularity as a principle for excellence in anything?

Of course there are ways of studying a painting, he concedes, that result in worthwhile insights that cant be described as scientific. But, he tells me, I think the humanities would do themselves a favour by not insisting on staying in a silo. If they are wanting to attract the smartest minds from the next generation, it would be wise to hold out the promise that there will be new ways of understanding things the same expansive mindset that attracts smart, ambitious people to the sciences could also attract them to the humanities.

That it isnt just a question of reinterpreting the same works of art, with the same methods, over and over again, he concludes. I dont see why humanistic scholarship cant make progress. Wieseltier seemed to insist that it cant, but I dont think most people in the humanities would agree with this. He claims to speak for the humanities. But I can imagine a lot of people in the humanities saying: Speak for yourself!

Pinker was born in 1954 in Montral, and raised in that bilingual citys English-speaking Jewish community (his sister, Susan, is also a psychologist, of the clinical rather than research variety). Its tempting to try to attribute his subsequent intellectual interests to the milieu of his upbringing. Did his focus on language emerge from having grown up in a linguistic battleground? Did his conception of the mind as a complex assemblage of modules, each designed for specific purposes, arise from inspecting the machines his grandfather used as a garment manufacturer? Was it growing up in the 1960s, when many progressives embraced a blank slate model of humans as a precondition for radical change, that prompted him to rebel against that notion in his work?

Such speculation can be hazardous when it concerns an evolutionary psychologist who believes that genetic heritage is more important than parenting or peer-group influence. But how far, really, does Pinker believes his career trajectory was influenced by his genes, and how far by his upbringing?

There are parallel universes to this one [in which] I wouldnt have written The Better Angels of Our Nature or The Language Instinct, he says. But Id probably be in the sciences of something human. I probably wouldnt have been a physicist: Im too much of a yenta, too interested in humans. On the other hand, I probably wouldnt have been a literary critic.

In this universe, Pinker studied experimental psychology at McGill University in Montral, then did his PhD in the same field at Harvard; he has spent the rest of his career there and at MIT, just down the street.

Wherever he got them from, Pinkers dispositions include a prodigious appetite for work. As well as being a self-confessed micromanager in his teaching work, as Harvards Johnstone Family Professor of Psychology, hes usually either pursuing a full schedule of research, speaking and article-writing, or plunging into months-long marathons of book-writing.

When I write a book, its almost all-consuming, he says, recalling the year he spent in his house on Cape Cod writing The Better Angels, seven days a week, and sometimes until three in the morning. (Hed spent the previous year doing little but reading in preparation for it.) I do try to exercise. I try to spend some time being a human being with my wife as recreation, he and Goldstein ride a tandem bicycle and paddle a tandem kayak. Fortunately, shes also a very intense writer, so she sympathises.

The couple do not have children, a fact Pinker sometimes uses to illustrate the non-determinative nature of genetic predispositions. (He might be predisposed, thanks to natural selection, to reproduce,but hes used his frontal lobe, a crucial part of his evolutionary inheritance, to decide not to.) Some things have to give, Pinker says. Im not on Facebook, I dont see a whole lot of movies, I dont watch much TV not because I consider myself above TV, I just dont have time. And I dont have a whole lot of face-to-face meetings. The PinkerGoldstein house is sometimes almost silent, except for keyboard-tapping, for days and weeks on end.

Both partners are self-described, out-and-proud atheists. Yet while Pinker has received awards from atheist organisations for his support for their cause, its notable that he opts not to focus on religion, or its opponents, in his work. A Pinker book on the topic would surely have sold impressively, anointing him the fifth horseman of New Atheism but theres just not enough intellectual content in there, at least on mind, for me to explore, he says. I think [Richard] Dawkins has done a fine job; I dont think I have anything to add to that.

Pinkers relative lack of engagement in the modern wars over belief shouldnt be taken as any endorsement of Stephen Jay Goulds argument that religion and science are non-overlapping magisteria, each a legitimate domain of authority that should keep out of the others business. As a matter of fact, Pinker says, religions have concerned themselves with the subject-matter of scienceAll the worlds major religions have origin myths, they have theories of psychology, of what animates a body that allows it to make decisions. And I think science has competed on that territory successfully: it has shown that those explanations are factually incorrect.

Does any kind of spirituality, however non-religiously defined, play a role in his life?

Im afraid of using the word spiritual, he says. I mean, I have a sense of awe and wonder a sense of intellectual vertigo in pondering certain questions. I hesitate to use the word spiritual just because it comes with so much baggage about the supernatural.

Pinkers next book, The Sense of Style, will be a style manual for writers incorporating insights from cognitive psychology and linguistics. For example, it will offer advice on how to get around the curse of knowledge the difficulty writers face in being unable to place themselves in the mind of a reader who doesnt already know as much as the writer knows. Or the question of how to relate to ones imagined reader: insights from psychology, Pinker will argue, show that the appropriate metaphor to keep in mind is one of vision that the stance you take as a writer ought to be to pretend that youre pointing out something in the world that your reader could see with his own eyes if only he were given an unobstructed view.

To the extent that these, or any other findings, rely on explanations from evolutionary psychology, theyre vulnerable to a recurrent criticism: arent evolutionary psychologists guilty of simply constructing retrospectively satisfying just-so stories, with no way of showing whether or not theyre the truth?

In one memorable passage in How the Mind Works, Pinker suggests that our cultural tendency to reward successful executives (and Harvard academics) with high-floor offices might result from an adaptive preference for good views of the surrounding territory, the better to defend against attackers. But in an alternative world where we rewarded executives with offices in the basement, couldnt you construct a mirror-image explanation, about the benefits of being able to hide out of sight?

For Pinker, the crucial question is whether a hypothesis can be tested. First, he says, youd have to establish by means of psychology experiments, or surveys of property prices that there was indeed a culturally widespread, present-day preference for high floors with good views. Then youd have to scour the historical evidence: for example, data from studies of tribal warfare, on whether theres been a historically continued preference for high vantage points over bunkers and burrows. Sufficient data showing a preference through history and across cultures, and in contexts of life and death, might amount to good reason to accept your hypothesis.

Once more, Pinker navigates his way through my critique with ease. All attempts to puncture his unique brand of rational optimism his confidence that careful scientific thinking, consistently applied, will carry humanity towards a future of reason, peace and flourishing end in failure.

Even climate change, that archetypal case of humanity remaining inert in the face of scientific knowledge, doesnt do it. I think it would be foolhardy to say well solve it, but I dont think its foolhardy to say we can solve it, Pinker says. History tells us there have been cases in which the global community has adopted agreements to better collective welfare: the ban on atmospheric nuclear testing would be an example. The ban on commercial whaling. The end of piracy and privateering as a legitimate form of international competition. The banning of chlorofluorocarbons.

In this domain as elsewhere, in Pinkers judgement, science plus judicious optimism may yet win the day. Or, as he puts it: Were not on a trolley-track to oblivion.

Extra

Pinker on the Berlin Wall

In short, its not hard to find anecdotes that seem to contradict a guiding principle behind much of Pinkers work which is that science and human reason are, slowly but unmistakably, making the world a better place.

Repeatedly during our conversation, I seek to puncture the silver-haired professors quietly relentless optimism. If the ongoing tolls of war and violence cant do it, what about the prevalence in America of unscientific beliefs about the origins of life? Or the devastating potential impacts of climate change, paired with the news also released in the week we meet that 23 per cent of Americans dont believe its happening, up seven percentage points in just eight months?

I try. But it proves far from easy.

At first glance Pinkers implacable optimism, though in keeping with his sunny demeanour and stereotypically Canadian friendliness, presents a puzzle. His stellar career which includes two Pulitzer Prize nominations for his books How the Mind Works (1997) and The Blank Slate: The modern denial of human nature (2002) has been defined, above all, by support for the fraught notion of human nature: the contention that genetic predispositions account in hugely significant ways for how we think, feel and act, why we behave towards others as we do, and why we excel in certain areas rather than others.

This has frequently drawn Pinker into controversy as in 2005, when he offered a defence of Larry Summers, then Harvards President, who had suggested that the under-representation of women in science and maths careers might be down to innate sex differences.

The possibility that men and women might differ for reasons other than socialisation, expectations, hidden biases and barriers is very close to an absolute taboo, Pinker tells me. He faults books such as Lean In, by Facebooks chief operating officer, Sheryl Sandberg, for not entertaining the notion that men and women might not have identical life desires. But he also insists that taking the possibility of such differences seriously need not lend any justification to policies or prejudices that exclude women from positions of expertise or power.

Even if there are sex differences, theyre differences in the means of two overlapping populations, so for any [stereotypically female] trait you care to name, therell be many men who are more extreme than most women, and vice versa. So as a matter of both efficiency and of fairness, you should treat every individual as an individual, and not prejudge them.

It is generally assumed that anyone who takes human nature seriously will be a fatalist, and probably politically conservative. If were pre-wired to be how we are, the reasoning goes, we might as well accept it and give up on hopes of any change. One way of interpreting Pinkers most recent book, The Better Angels of Our Nature, is as an 800-page doorstopper of a riposte to this idea. Not only can we change, but when it comes to arguably the most important measure of improvement the violence we inflict on each other we actually have changed, to an almost incredible degree.
Audio titled steven-pinker-better-angels

I had very often come across the objection that if human nature exists including some ugly motives like revenge, dominance, greed and lust then that would imply its pointless to try to improve the human condition, because humans are innately depraved, says the 59-year-old, whose distinctive appearance today he is sporting black cowboy boots frequently gets him stopped in the street. Or theres an alternative objection: that we ought to improve our lot, and therefore, it cannot be the case that human nature exists.

Pinker puts all this down to a fear that acknowledging human nature would subvert any attempt to improve the human condition. Better Angels argues that this is a misunderstanding of what human nature means. It shouldnt be identified with a certain set of behaviours; rather, we have a complex variety of predispositions, violent and peaceful, that can be activated in different ways by different environments. The books title, drawn from Abraham Lincolns first inaugural address, is a poetic allusion to the parts of human nature that can overcome the nastier parts, he explains.

But Better Angels is notable above all for the sheer weight of evidence it amasses, culled from forensic archaeology, government statistics, town records, and studies by atrocitologists of historical genocides and other mass killings. The book demonstrates that homicides, calculated as a proportion of the worlds population at any given point, have plummeted; when you look at the numbers this way, World War II wasnt the worst single atrocity in history, but more like the tenth.

Pinker dwells, in sometimes unnerving detail, on horrifying methods of torture once considered routine. The Heretics Fork had a pair of sharp spikes at each end, he writes, in what is definitely not the most appalling passage. One end was propped under the victims jaw and the other at the base of his neck, so that as his muscles became exhausted he would impale himself in both places.

Human nature or no human nature, Pinker says, its just a brute fact that we dont throw virgins into volcanoes any more. We dont execute people for shoplifting a cabbage. And we used to.

He offers a multi-pronged explanation for this decline, from the rise of the state and of cities, to literacy, trade and democracy. Whether this constitutes an across-the-board endorsement of scientific rationality may be debated. (Like other latter-day partisans of Enlightenment values, the critic John Gray wrote, Pinker prefers to ignore the fact that many Enlightenment thinkers have been doctrinally anti-liberal, while quite a few have favoured the large-scale use of political violence.) But its hard to question the basic finding that your chances of meeting a sticky end, all else being equal, are vastly lower in 2014 than they were in 1014.

If Pinkers message has proved hard for some to swallow, that may be because our standards are improving even faster than our actual behaviour, giving the misleading impression that things are getting worse. Hate attacks on Muslims are deplorable, and they ought to be combated, and it reflects well that were concerned when they do occur, Pinker says. But by the standards of past pogroms and ethnic cleansings, theyre in the noise: this is not a phenomenon of the same magnitude as the ethnic expulsions of decades past.

Weve even witnessed the emergence of whole new categories of condemnable acts. Take bullying, says Pinker: The President of the United States gave a speech denouncing bullying! When I was a child, this would have been worthy of satire. As we continue to construct a social environment that activates more and more of our peaceable dispositions, and fewer and fewer of our aggressive ones, the remaining instances of bad behaviour stick out like ever-sorer thumbs.

Whats more, evolutionary psychology, one of Pinkers several specialisms, can explain why. For reasons that long ago made excellent sense, our brains are adapted to focus on bad news over good, vivid threats over vague ones, and recent horrors over historically distant atrocities. Our elevated levels of anxiety about the future might actually be a sign of reasons triumph.

It could be interpreted as a sign of our growing up, Pinker says. We worry about more things, because we know that there are more things to worry about. Every time we go to a restaurant, we worry we might be ingesting saturated fats, or carcinogens. For my parents generation, the main concern about food was: Does it taste delicious?

Many of Pinkers most ambitious ideas about science and human morality have their origins in a seemingly trivial observation about irregular verbs. Building on the groundbreaking linguistic ideas of Noam Chomsky, Pinker proposed that certain simple language errors committed by young children capture the essence of language itself.

When a three-year-old says I eated the ice cream or we holded the kittens, she is, Pinker observes, following a grammar rule correctly, and making a mistake only because we happen to suspend the rule for those verbs in English. Since she couldnt have learned eated or holded by simply imitating adult speakers, this points to the presence of innate cognitive machinery a language instinct, to quote the title of Pinkers 1994 book that enables a young child to construct novel linguistic forms by following rules.

(Irregular verbs have an even more intimate role in Pinkers life: he met his wife, the philosopher Rebecca Goldstein, through an email exchange after he mentioned her correct use of the past participle stridden in his book Words and Rules.)

Years later, in 2007s The Stuff of Thought, he extended this reasoning to the structures of mentalese, the wordless language of thought that he argues we use to think in. When, for example, we use spatial language to talk about time as in a long day, or bringing a meeting forward might we be relying on an in-built, pre-linguistic tendency to think about the abstract notion of time by analogy to space, something far more concretely graspable to an early human concerned with food, shelter and survival?

This view of the mind as a set of modules evolved to confront specific cognitive challenges on the Pleistocene savannah is most ambitiously on display in How the Mind Works, a dazzling effort to reverse engineer all of our mental capacities, asking for what purposes each might have been selected. Love, humour, war, jealousy, the disgust we feel at the idea of eating certain animals but not others, religous food taboos, compulsive lying: none of them escape the blade of Pinkers rationalist scalpel.

Assuming you buy the books general approach, it is almost impossible after reading it to cling to the romantic notion that there might be more to our inner lives than the brute facts of biology and natural selection. The notable exception is how the brain causes sentience, or conscious awareness: after a long discussion on the topic,Pinker finally concludes: Beats me! Theres reason to believe, he argues, that humans may simply lack the mental capacity ever to solve the mindbody problem.

But the broader philosophical question how far science can, or should, reach into the life of the mind got a disputatious airing last year, when Pinker wrote an essay for the New Republic entitled Science is not your enemy. It was motivated in part by reports on both sides of the Atlantic about declining student enrolments in humanities subjects, and was Pinkers intervention in the long-running debate over scientism: are science and scientists guilty of attempting to colonise areas of intellectual life where they dont belong?

Rather than denying that this was a real phenomenon, as numerous scientists have, Pinker audaciously claimed it was a good thing providing you defined scientism correctly. Humanities scholars had themselves to blame, he implied, for the decline of their fields: by insisting on remaining inside departmental silos, resistant to new approaches, theyd helped guarantee their growing irrelevance. Science was not engaged upon an imperialistic drive to occupy the humanities, he wrote. The promise of science is to enrich and diversify the intellectual tools of humanistic scholarship, not to obliterate them.

In a furious response, entitled Crimes against humanities, the New Republics literary editor, Leon Wieseltier, accused Pinker of denying the very possibility of valid yet non-scientific knowledge. How absurd, he argued, to imagine that a scientific analysis of a painting a chemical breakdown of its pigments and textures, and so on could be the only thing worth saying about it. Pinker calls this a paranoid interpretation of his argument. How could an understanding of perception of colour, of form, of lighting, of shading, of content such as faces and landscapes not enrich our understanding of art?

Yet if Wieseltiers retort was overheated, he may still have a point. Pinker wasnt and isnt merely calling on scholars from different disciplines to talk to each other more. His argument is that any scholar committed to the idea that the world is intelligible is doing science. The great thinkers of the Age of Reason and the Enlightenment were scientists, he wrote, naming various philosophers.

It seems to follow from this that non-scientific scholarship doesnt help make the world intelligible, but Pinker will have none of it. Im married to a humanities scholar. I collaborate with humanities scholars. Im in fields like linguistics, where deans dont know whether its the humanities or not, he says. Many humanities scholars particularly here at Harvard and MIT, but elsewhere too find it very exciting that there might be new ways of approaching old problems, and an influx of new ideas. I mean, who in their right mind could defend insularity as a principle for excellence in anything?

Of course there are ways of studying a painting, he concedes, that result in worthwhile insights that cant be described as scientific. But, he tells me, I think the humanities would do themselves a favour by not insisting on staying in a silo. If they are wanting to attract the smartest minds from the next generation, it would be wise to hold out the promise that there will be new ways of understanding things the same expansive mindset that attracts smart, ambitious people to the sciences could also attract them to the humanities.

That it isnt just a question of reinterpreting the same works of art, with the same methods, over and over again, he concludes. I dont see why humanistic scholarship cant make progress. Wieseltier seemed to insist that it cant, but I dont think most people in the humanities would agree with this. He claims to speak for the humanities. But I can imagine a lot of people in the humanities saying: Speak for yourself!

Pinker was born in 1954 in Montral, and raised in that bilingual citys English-speaking Jewish community (his sister, Susan, is also a psychologist, of the clinical rather than research variety). Its tempting to try to attribute his subsequent intellectual interests to the milieu of his upbringing. Did his focus on language emerge from having grown up in a linguistic battleground? Did his conception of the mind as a complex assemblage of modules, each designed for specific purposes, arise from inspecting the machines his grandfather used as a garment manufacturer? Was it growing up in the 1960s, when many progressives embraced a blank slate model of humans as a precondition for radical change, that prompted him to rebel against that notion in his work?

Such speculation can be hazardous when it concerns an evolutionary psychologist who believes that genetic heritage is more important than parenting or peer-group influence. But how far, really, does Pinker believes his career trajectory was influenced by his genes, and how far by his upbringing?

There are parallel universes to this one [in which] I wouldnt have written The Better Angels of Our Nature or The Language Instinct, he says. But Id probably be in the sciences of something human. I probably wouldnt have been a physicist: Im too much of a yenta, too interested in humans. On the other hand, I probably wouldnt have been a literary critic.

In this universe, Pinker studied experimental psychology at McGill University in Montral, then did his PhD in the same field at Harvard; he has spent the rest of his career there and at MIT, just down the street.

Wherever he got them from, Pinkers dispositions include a prodigious appetite for work. As well as being a self-confessed micromanager in his teaching work, as Harvards Johnstone Family Professor of Psychology, hes usually either pursuing a full schedule of research, speaking and article-writing, or plunging into months-long marathons of book-writing.

When I write a book, its almost all-consuming, he says, recalling the year he spent in his house on Cape Cod writing The Better Angels, seven days a week, and sometimes until three in the morning. (Hed spent the previous year doing little but reading in preparation for it.) I do try to exercise. I try to spend some time being a human being with my wife as recreation, he and Goldstein ride a tandem bicycle and paddle a tandem kayak. Fortunately, shes also a very intense writer, so she sympathises.

The couple do not have children, a fact Pinker sometimes uses to illustrate the non-determinative nature of genetic predispositions. (He might be predisposed, thanks to natural selection, to reproduce,but hes used his frontal lobe, a crucial part of his evolutionary inheritance, to decide not to.) Some things have to give, Pinker says. Im not on Facebook, I dont see a whole lot of movies, I dont watch much TV not because I consider myself above TV, I just dont have time. And I dont have a whole lot of face-to-face meetings. The PinkerGoldstein house is sometimes almost silent, except for keyboard-tapping, for days and weeks on end.

Both partners are self-described, out-and-proud atheists. Yet while Pinker has received awards from atheist organisations for his support for their cause, its notable that he opts not to focus on religion, or its opponents, in his work. A Pinker book on the topic would surely have sold impressively, anointing him the fifth horseman of New Atheism but theres just not enough intellectual content in there, at least on mind, for me to explore, he says. I think [Richard] Dawkins has done a fine job; I dont think I have anything to add to that.

Pinkers relative lack of engagement in the modern wars over belief shouldnt be taken as any endorsement of Stephen Jay Goulds argument that religion and science are non-overlapping magisteria, each a legitimate domain of authority that should keep out of the others business. As a matter of fact, Pinker says, religions have concerned themselves with the subject-matter of scienceAll the worlds major religions have origin myths, they have theories of psychology, of what animates a body that allows it to make decisions. And I think science has competed on that territory successfully: it has shown that those explanations are factually incorrect.
Audio titled steven-pinker-religion-science

Does any kind of spirituality, however non-religiously defined, play a role in his life?

Im afraid of using the word spiritual, he says. I mean, I have a sense of awe and wonder a sense of intellectual vertigo in pondering certain questions. I hesitate to use the word spiritual just because it comes with so much baggage about the supernatural.

Pinkers next book, The Sense of Style, will be a style manual for writers incorporating insights from cognitive psychology and linguistics. For example, it will offer advice on how to get around the curse of knowledge the difficulty writers face in being unable to place themselves in the mind of a reader who doesnt already know as much as the writer knows. Or the question of how to relate to ones imagined reader: insights from psychology, Pinker will argue, show that the appropriate metaphor to keep in mind is one of vision that the stance you take as a writer ought to be to pretend that youre pointing out something in the world that your reader could see with his own eyes if only he were given an unobstructed view.

To the extent that these, or any other findings, rely on explanations from evolutionary psychology, theyre vulnerable to a recurrent criticism: arent evolutionary psychologists guilty of simply constructing retrospectively satisfying just-so stories, with no way of showing whether or not theyre the truth?

In one memorable passage in How the Mind Works, Pinker suggests that our cultural tendency to reward successful executives (and Harvard academics) with high-floor offices might result from an adaptive preference for good views of the surrounding territory, the better to defend against attackers. But in an alternative world where we rewarded executives with offices in the basement, couldnt you construct a mirror-image explanation, about the benefits of being able to hide out of sight?

For Pinker, the crucial question is whether a hypothesis can be tested. First, he says, youd have to establish by means of psychology experiments, or surveys of property prices that there was indeed a culturally widespread, present-day preference for high floors with good views. Then youd have to scour the historical evidence: for example, data from studies of tribal warfare, on whether theres been a historically continued preference for high vantage points over bunkers and burrows. Sufficient data showing a preference through history and across cultures, and in contexts of life and death, might amount to good reason to accept your hypothesis.

Once more, Pinker navigates his way through my critique with ease. All attempts to puncture his unique brand of rational optimism his confidence that careful scientific thinking, consistently applied, will carry humanity towards a future of reason, peace and flourishing end in failure.

Even climate change, that archetypal case of humanity remaining inert in the face of scientific knowledge, doesnt do it. I think it would be foolhardy to say well solve it, but I dont think its foolhardy to say we can solve it, Pinker says. History tells us there have been cases in which the global community has adopted agreements to better collective welfare: the ban on atmospheric nuclear testing would be an example. The ban on commercial whaling. The end of piracy and privateering as a legitimate form of international competition. The banning of chlorofluorocarbons.

In this domain as elsewhere, in Pinkers judgement, science plus judicious optimism may yet win the day. Or, as he puts it: Were not on a trolley-track to oblivion.

This article first appeared on Mosaic and is republished here under a Creative Commons licence.

Talk to you soon.

If you believe in the work we are doing here at The Good Men Project and want to join our calls on a regular basis, please join us as a Premium Member, today.

All Premium Members get to view The Good Men Project with NO ADS.

Need more info? A complete list of benefits is here.

Photo credit: Istockphoto.com

The post In Conversation With Steven Pinker appeared first on The Good Men Project.

Related Posts


Share this post



← Older Post Newer Post →